A New Whistleblower Ethic (Part 1)
For years after her decision to disclose a wrongdoing, the
whistleblower will wrestle with the question whether she should have made her
disclosures for reasons beyond the practical considerations of financial and emotional
costs. Debate over whether whistleblowers
are heroes or villains points to the question of the ethics of
whistleblowing.
The existing whistleblower ethic constrains whistleblowing because
it violates an employee’s duty of loyalty to her employer and it might hurt the
organization and her colleagues[1]. Famously, Richard T. de George[2]
advised that external whistleblowing is morally permissible (but not required) if:
1.
The organization will seriously harm its
employees or the public
2.
The observer of the wrongdoing has reported it
to her supervisor
3.
If the supervisor failed to act, the observer
has exhausted all internal reporting options, including notifying the board of directors
After she has taken those three steps, she becomes morally
obligated to report the matter externally if:
4.
She has documented evidence that would convince
an objective person that the wrong is serious danger to the public
5.
She has good reason to believe that going public
will lead to the necessary changes and will be worth the risk of retaliation.
I propose that de George’s initial assumption of loyalty to
the organization is faulty. I contend
that the organization’s at-will employment policy, its retaliations against
dissenters, and its wrongdoings destroyed any bonds of loyalty that might have
existed before the whistleblower was thrown into her project.
Whether company loyalty is deserved as de George believes or
doubted as others contend[3],
different loyalties and higher duties can inspire the whistleblower – including
the company’s mission, the community or public good, family, professional
standards, and ethical or religious principles[4]. But just as philosophical reasoning follows,
rather than leads, our decisions[5],
appeals to duty, such as to family, can be cited to discourage whistleblowing or,
in the case of professional values, to encourage it.
I suggest that possible harm to the organization should not
affect the whistleblower’s calculations.
In the history of whistleblowing, firms that have been hurt
significantly by whistleblowing are far outnumbered by those that escaped
penalty entirely or that settled suits with modest fines and the denial of any
guilt. If a firm does cease to exist
following a whistleblower’s actions, its legitimate business activities will be
taken up by competitors, illegitimate activities will be discontinued as they
should be, and employees will move to other firms as they probably should have
done earlier. In the case of a nonprofit
like HomeFirst, financial failure would mean only the transfer of contracts,
assets, and employees to other nonprofits with little real disruption to the
community.
De George limits ethical whistleblowing to behavior that causes
serious and considerable harm, but that restriction gives too much room to
corporations that claim their wrongs were not serious at all. Too often a wrong – a theft, an act of sexual
harassment, a lie to the public – can seem minor in itself but is part of a
pattern of wrongdoing with broader effects.
One example: the robo-signings and irresponsible credit
verifications that Bank of America and other banks claimed were actions limited
to a few individuals or offices although together they contributed to the 2007
financial crisis[6]. Another: Volkswagen’s emissions test fraud
was the product of many bureaucratic decisions made in offices around the world
but now appear to have been supported by the company’s senior management[7]. HomeFirst contended that the wrongs I alleged
were minor or not
even real, yet they composed a pattern
of greater concern.
De George calls on the whistleblower to work her way through
her chain of command, giving superiors adequate opportunity to fix the problem,
as do some state laws[8]. The history of whistleblowing has made clear
the painful consequences of following his advice. The retaliations come in many forms, many of
which are difficult or impossible to prove, leaving the whistleblower defenseless
and the wrongdoer unpunished. By
identifying problems, the whistleblower shows herself to be an untrustworthy employee;
she seeds doubts about her reliability in concealing other misdeeds and her
ability to be a team player. Once she
suggests that something is wrong – not inefficient or unprofitable, but wrong –
she identifies herself has having standards potentially at odds with the
organization’s.
De George’s moral expectation that the whistleblower will
stand up if she has clear, convincing evidence seems commonsensical. If you have good, solid evidence, you should
share it with authorities. But evidence
is seldom as clear and convincing as it initially seems to the
whistleblower. Wrongdoers will resist
the introduction of evidence on grounds of confidentiality. Even after it is presented, evidence is subject
to conflicting interpretations, or it is contested with conflicting
evidence. The evaluation of evidence is
necessarily subject to personal and politically-influenced biases, which in
history have disadvantaged whistleblowers[9].
Nearly every whistleblower begins with the belief that her
disclosure will begin a process of correction in the organization. But whistleblowers are too often disappointed. In media accounts, whistleblower successes
are those where the employee receives some compensation for the retaliation she
suffered. Correction of the wrongdoing
is seldom discussed, and the organization seldom admits to having done wrong even
if a penalty is paid. Of the ten issues
that I raised at HomeFirst (the eight
alleged violations and the failures to repay the City
of San Jose and HUD),
only two resulted in minor changes in company behavior after more than two
years.
The federal and state protections offered to whistleblowers intensifies
the moral obligation, in de George’s view, for observers to disclose wrongs. The protections, though, are rarely
effective. A potential whistleblower cannot
know she will be protected from the consequences of her whistleblowing any more
than she can know that her whistleblowing will do any good. It is far easier for the ethicist on the
sidelines to claim that a person is morally required to make a disclosure than
for the whistleblower herself to know what she should do.
The existing ethical guidelines for those who consider whistleblowing
seem to me grossly out of touch with the reality faced by whistleblowers. Even if advice is ambiguous or suspect, the witness
must still choose for herself what action to take[10]. In response to that dilemma, I suggest that a
new whistleblowing ethic is needed.
[1] Hoffman, Michael W. and Mark S.
Schwartz. “The Morality of Whistleblowing: A
Commentary on Richard T. De George.” Journal of Business Ethics 127 (2015):771-781
[2] De George, Richard T. Business
Ethics. 6th edition. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Pearson
Education. 2006
[3] For example, Duska, Ronald. “Whistleblowing and Employee Loyalty.” In Contemporary
Issues in Business Ethics. DesJardins, Joseph R. and John J.
McCall (eds.) Belmont, California: Wadsworth Publishing Company. 1985. And Larmer, Robert
A. “Whistleblowing
and Employee Loyalty.” Journal of Business Ethics. 11.2 (Feb
1992): 125-128
[4] Ewin, R.E. “Corporate
Loyalty: Its Objects and Its Grounds.” Journal of Business
Ethics 12 (1993): 387-396. Johnson, Roberta Ann. Whistleblowing: When It
Works and Why. Boulder: Lynne Rienner
Publishers. 2003
[5] Knobe, Joshua, Wesley Buckwalter, Shaun Nichols,
Philip Robbins, Hagop Sarkissian and Tamler Sommers. “Experimental
Philosophy.”
Annual Review of Psychology 63 (2012): 81-99.
Alexander, Joshua. Experimental Philosophy: an Introduction. Cambridge UK: Polity. 2012
[6] Weise, Karen. “Mortgage Fraud Whistle-Blower Lynn Szymoniak
Exposed Robosigning’s Sins.” Bloomberg
News, September 12, 2013.
[7] Ewing, Jack. “Volkswagen Says 11 Million Cars Worldwide
Are Affected in Diesel Deception.” New York Times. September 22, 2015. Ewing, Jack, and Hiroko Tabuchi. “Volkswagen
Scandal Reaches All the Way to the Top, Lawsuits Say.” New York Times. July 19, 2016.
[8] For
example, Florida,
Indiana,
Louisiana,
New
Hampshire, and New
York. In addition, the State
of California investigator seemed disturbed that I had reported problems
without letting HomeFirst take care of them.
[9] Moberly, Richard. “Sarbanes-Oxley’s Whistleblower Provisions:
Ten Years Later.” South Carolina Law Review, volume 64,
number 1, Autumn 2012, p. 2-54.
[10] Bouville, Mathieu. “Whistle-blowing and morality.”
Journal of Business Ethics. 81.3
(September 2008): 579-585
No comments:
Post a Comment